If employers of labour were offered money-capital at half the
present rate of interest, the yield of every other class of capital would soon
also fall to half. If, for example, interest on the money borrowed to build a
house is less than the rent of a similar existing house, or if it is more
profitable to bring a waste into cultivation than to rent similar farmland,
competition must inevitably reduce house and farm rents to the level of the
reduced interest on money. For the surest method of depreciating material
capital (a house, a field) is obviously to create and operate additional
material capital alongside it. But it is a law of economics that increased
production increases the mass of available money-capital. This tends to raise
wages and finally to reduce interest to zero.
Proudhon: What is Property ?
The abolition of unearned income, of so-called surplus-value also termed
interest and rent, is the immediate economic aim of every socialistic movement.
The method generally proposed for the attainment of this aim is communism in the
shape of nationalisation or socialisation of production. I know of only one
socialist - Pierre Joseph Proudhon - whose investigations into the nature of
capital point to the possibility of another solution of the problem. The demand
for nationalisation of production is advocated on the plea that the nature of
the means of production necessitates it. It is usually asserted off-hand, as a
truism, that ownership of the means of production must necessarily in all
circumstances give the capitalist the upper hand when bargaining with the
workers about wages - an advantage represented, and destined eternally to be
represented, by " surplus-value" or capital-interest. No one, except
Proudhon, was able to conceive that the preponderance now manifestly on the side
of property can be shifted to the side of the dispossessed (the workers), simply
by the construction of a new house beside every existing house, of a new factory
beside every factory already established.
Proudhon showed socialists over fifty years ago that uninterrupted hard work is
the only method of successfully attacking capital. But this truth is even
further from their comprehension to-day than it was in Proudhon's time.
Proudhon, indeed, has not been entirely forgotten, but he has never been
properly understood. If his advice had been understood and acted on, there would
now be no such thing as capital. Because he was mistaken in his method (the
exchange banks), his theory as a whole was discredited.
How was it that the Marxian theory of capital succeeded in ousting that of
Proudhon and in giving sovereign sway to cornmunistic socialism ? How is it that
Marx and his theory are spoken of by every newspaper in the world ? Some have
suggested as a reason the hopelessness, and the corresponding harmlessness, of
the Marxian doctrine. "No capitalist is afraid of his theory, just as no
capitalist is afraid of the Christian doctrine; it is therefore positively an
advantage to capital to have Marx and Christ discussed as widely as possible,
for Marx can never damage capital. But beware of Proudhon; better keep him out
of sight and hearing! He is a dangerous fellow since there is no denying the
truth of his contention that if the workers were allowed to remain at work
without hindrance, disturbance or interruption, capital would soon be choked by
an over-supply of capital (not to be confused with an over-production of goods).
Proudhon's suggestion for attacking capital is a dangerous one, since it can be
put into practice forth-with. The Marxian programme speaks of the tremendous
productive capacity of the present-day trained worker equipped with modem
machinery and tools, but Marx cannot put this tremendous productive capacity to
use, whereas in the hands of Proudhon it becomes a deadly weapon against
capital. Therefore talk away, harp on Marx, so that Proudhon may be forgotten."
This explanation is plausible. And is not the same true of Henry George's
land-reform movement ? The landowners soon discovered that this was a sheep in
wolf's clothing; that the taxation of rent on land could not be carried out in
an effective form and that the man and his reform were therefore harmless. The
Press was allowed to advertise Henry George’s Utopia, and land-reformers were
everywhere received in the best society. Every German "agrarian" and
speculator in corn-duties turned single-taxer. The lion was toothless, so it was
safe to play with him, just as many persons of fashion are pleased to play with
Christian principles.
Marx's examination of capital goes astray at the outset.
Marx succumbs to a popular fallacy and holds that capital consists of material
goods. For Proudhon, on the contrary, interest is not the product of material
goods, but of an economic situation, a condition of the market.
Marx regards surplus-value as spoil resulting from the abuse of a power
conferred by ownership. For Proudhon surplus-value is subject to the law of
demand and supply.
According to Marx, surplus-value must invariably be positive. For Proudhon the
possibility of negative surplus-value must be taken into consideration.
(Positive surplus-value is surplus-value on the side of supply, that is, of the
capitalist, negative surplus-value is surplus-value on the side of labour).
Marx's remedy is the political supremacy of the dispossessed, to be achieved by
means of organisation. Proudhon's remedy is the removal of the obstacles
preventing us from the full development of our productive capacity.
For Marx, strikes and crises are welcome occurrences, and the final forcible
expropriation of the expropriators is the means to the end. Proudhon, on the
contrary, says: On no account allow yourselves to be deterred from work, for the
most powerful allies of capital are strikes, crises and unemployment; whereas
nothing is more fatal to it than hard work.
Marx says: Strikes and crises will sweep you along towards your goal; the great
collapse will land you in paradise. - No, says Proudhon, that is humbug, methods
of that kind carry you away from your goal. With such tactics you will never
filch as much as one per cent from interest.
To Marx private ownership means power and supremacy. Proudhon, on the contrary,
recognises that this supremacy is rooted in money, and that under altered
conditions the power of private ownership may be transformed into weakness.
If, as Marx affirms, capital consists of material goods, possession of which
gives the capitalist his supremacy, any addition to these goods would
necessarily strengthen capital. If a load of hay or a barrowful of economic
literature weighs 100 lbs., two loads, two barrowfuls must weigh exactly 200 lbs.
Similarly if a house yields $1000 of surplus-value annually, ten houses added to
it must always, and as a matter of course, yield ten times $1000 - on the
assumption that capital consists simply of material goods.
Now we all know that capital cannot be added up like material goods, since
additional capital not infrequently diminishes the value of capital already
existing. The truth of this can be tested by daily observation. Under certain
circumstances the price of a ton of fish may be greater than the price of 100
tons. What price would air fetch, if it were not so plentiful ? As it is, we get
it gratis.
Not long before the outbreak of the war landlords in the suburbs of Berlin were
in despair about the decline of house-rents, that is, surplus-value, and the
capitalistic press was clamorous in denunciation of the
"building fury of the workers and contractors",
of the
"building plague rife in the housing industry."
(Quoted from the German Press.)
Are not these expressions a revelation of the precarious nature of capital ?
Capital, which Marxists hold in such awe, dies of the "building plague";
it decamps before the "building fury" of the workers! What would
Proudhon and Marx have advised in such a situation ? "Stop building",
Marx would have cried; "lament, go abegging, bemoan your unemployment,
declare a strike! For every house you build adds to the power of the capitalists
as sure as two and two make four. The power of capital is measured by
surplus-value, in this case house-rent; so the greater the number of houses the
more powerful, surely, is capital. Therefore let me advise you, limit your
output, agitate for an eight-hour or even a six-hour day, since every house you
build adds to house-rent and house-rent is surplus-value. Restrain, therefore,
your building fury, for the less you build, the more cheaply you'll be housed!"
Probably Marx would have shrunk from uttering such nonsense. But the Marxian
doctrine, which regards capital as a material commodity, misleads the workers
into thinking and acting on these lines.
Now listen to Proudhon: "Full steam ahead ! Let's have the building fury,
give us the building plague! Workers and employers, on no account let the trowel
be snatched from your hands. Down with all who attempt to interfere with your
work; they are your deadly enemies! Who are these that prate of a building
plague, of over-production in the housing industry, while house-rents still show
a trace of surplus-value, of capital-interest ? Let capital die of the building
plague! For some five years only have you been allowed to indulge in your
building fury, and already capitalists feel the pinch, already they are
lamenting the decline of surplus-value, rents have already dropped from 4 to 3 %
- that is, by a quarter. Three times five years more of untrammelled labour, and
you will be revelling in houses freed from surplus-value. Capital is dying, and
it is you who are killing it by your labour."
Truth is as sluggish as a crocodile in the mud of the eternal Nile. It does not
reck of time; time measured by the span of human life means nothing to it, since
it is everlasting. But truth has an agent which, mortal like man, is always
hurried. For this agent, time is money; it is ever busy and excited, and its
name is error. Error cannot afford to lie low and let the ages pass. It is
constantly giving and receiving hard knocks. It is in the way of everyone and
everyone is in its way. It is the true stumbling block.
Therefore it does not matter if Proudhon is taboo. His adversary Marx, with his
errors, takes good care that the truth shall come to light. And in this sense we
may say that Marx has become the agent of Proudhon. Proudhon in his grave is at
peace. His words have everlasting worth. But Marx must keep restlessly moving.
Some day, however, the truth will prevail and Marx's doctrines will be relegated
to the museum of human errors.
Even if Proudhon had really been suppressed and forgotten, the nature of capital
would still remain unchanged. The truth would be discovered by another; of the
discoverer's name truth takes no account.
The author of this book was led into the path pursued by Proudhon and came to
the same conclusions. Perhaps it was fortunate that he was ignorant of Proudhon's
theory of capital, for he was thus enabled to set about his work the more
independently, and independence is the best preparation for scientific inquiry.
The present author has been more fortunate than Proudhon. He discovered what
Proudhon had discovered fifty years earlier, namely the nature of capital, but
as well he discovered a practicable road to Proudhon's goal. And that, after all,
is what matters.
Proudhon asked: Why are we short of houses, machinery and ships ? And he also
gave the correct answer: Because money limits the building of them. Or, to use
his own words: "Because money is a sentinel posted at the entrance to the
markets, with orders to let no one pass. Money, you imagine, is the key that
opens the gates of the market (by which term is meant the exchange of products),
that is not true-money is the bolt that bars them."
Money simply will not suffer another house to be built in addition to every
existing house. As soon as capital ceases to yield the traditional interest,
money strikes and brings work to a standstill. Money, therefore, acts like a
serum against the "building-plague" and the "working fury".
It renders capital (houses, industrial plant, ships) immune from the menace of
its own increase.
Having discovered the barring or blocking nature of money, Proudhon raised the
slogan: Let us combat the privilege of money by raising goods and labour to the
level of money. For two privileges, if opposed, neutralise one another. By
attaching to goods the surplus weight now on the side of money, we make the two
weights balance.
Such was Proudhon's idea, and to put it into practice he founded the exchange
banks. As everyone knows, they failed.
And yet the solution of the problem which eluded Proudhon is simple enough. All
that is needed is to abandon the customary standpoint, the standpoint of the
possessor of money, and to look at the problem from the standpoint of labour and
of the possessor of goods. This shifting of the standpoint will let us grasp the
solution directly. Goods, not money, are the real foundation of economic life.
Goods and their compounds make up 99% of our wealth, money only 1%. Therefore
let us treat goods as we treat foundations; let us not tamper with them. We must
accept goods as they appear in the market. We cannot alter them. If they rot,
break, perish, let them do so; it is their nature. However efficiently we may
organise Proudhon's exchange banks, we cannot save the newspaper in the hands of
the newsvendor from being reduced, two hours later, to waste paper, if it fails
to find a purchaser. Moreover we must remember that money is a universal medium
of saving; all the money that serves commerce as a medium of exchange comes to
the savings banks and lies there until it is enticed into circulation again by
interest. And how can we ever raise goods to the level of ready money (gold) in
the eyes of savers ? How can we induce them, instead of saving money, to fill
their chests or store-rooms with straw, books, bacon, oil, hides, guano,
dynamite, porcelain ?
And yet this is what Proudhon really aimed at in attempting to bring goods and
money to a common level. Proudhon had overlooked the fact that money is not only
a medium of exchange, but also a medium of saving, and that money and potatoes,
money and lime, money and cloth can never in any circumstances be looked upon as
things of equal worth in the chests of the savers. A youth saving against old
age will prefer a single gold coin to the contents of the largest warehouse.
We cannot, therefore, tamper with goods, they are the primary factor to which
everything else must be adapted. But let us look a little more closely at money,
for here some alteration may prove feasible. Must money always remain what it is
at present ? Must money, as a commodity, be superior to the commodities which,
as medium of exchange, it is meant to serve ? In case of fire, flood, crisis,
war, changes of fashion and so forth, is money alone to be immune from damage ?
Why must money be superior to the goods which it is to serve ? And is not the
superiority of money to goods the privilege which we found to be the cause of
surplus-value, the privilege which Proudhon endeavoured to abolish ? Let us,
then, make an end of the privileges of money. Nobody, not even savers,
speculators, or capitalists, must find money, as a commodity, preferable to the
contents of the markets, shops, and warehouses. If money is not to hold sway
over goods, it must deteriorate, as they do. Let it be attacked by moth and rust,
let it sicken, let it run away; and when it comes to die let its possessor pay
to have the carcass flayed and buried. Then, and not till then, shall we be able
to say that money and goods are on an equal footing and perfect equivalents - as
Proudhon aimed at making them.
Let us put this demand in terms of a commercial formula. We say: The possessor
of goods, during the period of storage, invariably incurs a loss in quantity and
quality. Moreover he has to pay the cost of storage (rent, insurance, caretaking
and so on). What does all this amount to annually ? Say 5% - which is more
likely to be below than above the actual amount.
Now what depreciation has a banker, capitalist, or hoarder to debit to the money
in his possession or on loan ? By how much was the war-chest in the Julius Tower
at Spandau diminished in the course of the 44 years that it was stored there ?
Not by one penny !
That being so, the answer to our question is clear, we must subject money to the
loss to which goods are liable through the necessity of storage. Money is then
no longer superior to goods; it makes no difference to anyone whether he
possesses, or saves, money or goods. Money and goods are then perfect
equivalents, Proudhon's problem is solved and the fetters that have prevented
humanity from developing its full powers fall away.
As has been pointed out in the Introduction, the economic aim
of every kind of socialism is to abolish unearned income, so-called
surplus-value, sometimes termed rent and interest. To attain this end,
nationalisation or socialisation of production with all its consequences is
usually declared to be indispensable.
This claim of the dispossessed is supported by Karl Marx’s scientific
investigation into the nature of capital which attempts to prove that
surplus-value is an inseparable concomitant of private enterprise and private
ownership of the means of production.
The present writer proposes to demonstrate that this Marxian doctrine is based
on untenable premises which we must abandon in order to arrive at the truth. My
conclusions are to the effect that capital must not be looked upon as a material
commodity, but as a condition of the market, determined solely by demand and
supply. The French socialist Proudhon, the opponent of Marx, gave the workers
the proof of this more than 50 years ago.
Guided by this corrected theory of capital we shall learn that the removal of
certain artificial obstacles due to private ownership of land and our irrational
monetary system, will enable our present economic order to realise fully its
fundamentally sound principle. The removal of these obstacles will allow the
workers by their own labour and in a short time (ten to twenty years) so to
alter the market conditions for capital that surplus-value will disappear
completely and the means of production will lose their capitalistic character.
Private ownership of the means of production will then present no advantage
beyond that which the owner of a savings-box derives from its possession: the
savings-box does not yield him surplus-value or interest, but he can gradually
use up its contents.
The savings or other money then invested in means of production (house, ship,
factory) will be returned to the owners in the shape of sums annually written
off their value in proportion to their natural wear and tear or consumption.
Simply by means of untrammelled hard work fructified by the powerful modern
instruments of production, the great admired and dreaded tyrant capital will be
reduced to the harmless role of a child's porcelain savings-box. The savings-box
yields no surplus-value, and to get at the contents its owner must break it.
The first and second parts of this book, dealing with land, show how agriculture
and the building and mining industries can be carried on without surplus-value,
yet without communism. The later parts of the book, dealing with the new theory
of capital, show how, without nationalising the remaining means of production,
we can entirely eliminate surplus-value from our economic order and establish
the right to the whole proceeds of labour.
A worker in this book means anyone living on the proceeds of
his labour. By this definition farmers, employers, artisans, wage-earners,
artists, priests, soldiers, officials, kings, are workers. The antithesis of a
worker in our economic system is therefore the capitalist, the person in receipt
of unearned income.
We distinguish between the product of labour, the yield of labour and the
proceeds of labour. The product of labour is what is produced by labour. The
yield of labour is the money received through the sale of the product of labour
or as the result of the wage contract. The proceeds of labour mean what a worker,
out of the yield of his labour, can buy and convey to the place of consumption.
The terms: wages, fee, salary are used instead of the term yield of labour when
the product of labour is not a tangible object. Example: street-sweeping,
writing poems, governing. If the product of labour is a tangible object, say a
chair, and at the same time the property of the worker, the yield of labour is
not called a wage or salary, but the price of the object sold. All these
designations imply the same thing: the money-yield of the work done.
Manufacturers' and merchants' profits, after deduction of the capital interest
or rent usually contained in them, are likewise to be classed as yield of labour.
The manager of a mining company draws his salary exclusively for the work done
by him. If the manager is also a shareholder, his income will be increased by
the amount of the dividend received. He is then at once a worker and a
capitalist. As a rule the income of farmers, merchants and employers is made up
of the yield of their labour plus a certain quantity of rent or interest. A
farmer working on rented land with borrowed capital lives exclusively on the
proceeds of his labour. What is left to him of the product of his labour after
payment of rent and interest, is the result of his activity and is subject to
the general laws determining wages.
Between the product of labour (or service rendered) and the proceeds of labour
lie the various bargains which we strike daily in buying the commodities we
consume. These bargains greatly affect the proceeds of labour. It very commonly
happens that two persons offering the same product of labour for sale obtain
unequal proceeds of labour. The reason for this is that though equal as workers,
they are unequal as dealers. Some persons excel at disposing of their product
for a good price, and at making judicious choice when purchasing the commodities
they need. In the case of goods produced for the market, the commercial disposal
of them and the knowledge necessary for successful bargaining contribute as much
to the success of labour as does technical efficiency. The exchange of the
product must be considered as the final act of production. In so far every
worker is also a dealer.
If the objects composing the product of labour and those composing the proceeds
of labour had a common property by which they could be compared and measured,
commerce, that is, the conversion of the product of labour into the proceeds of
labour. might be dispensed with. Provided the measuring, counting or weighing
were accurate, the proceeds of labour would always be equal to the product of
labour (less interest and rent), and the proof that no sort of cheating had
taken place could be supplied by examination of the objects of the proceeds of
labour, just as one may asceration by one's own scales whether the druggist's
scales weigh correctly or not. Commodities have however no such common property.
The exchange is always effected by bargaining, never by the use of any kind of
measure. Nor does the use of money exempt us from the necessity of bargaining to
effect the exchange. The term "measure of value" sometimes applied to
money in antiquated writings on economics, is misleading. No quality of a canary
bird, a pill or an apple can be measured by a piece of money.
Hence a direct comparison between the product of labour and proceeds of labour
will not furnish any valid and legal proof as to whether the labourer has
received the whole proceeds of his labour. The right to the whole proceeds of
labour, if by that phrase we mean the individual's right to the whole proceeds
of his labour, must be relegated to the realm of imagination.
But it is very different with the common or collective right to the whole
proceeds of labour. This only implies that the proceeds of labour should be
divided exclusively among the workers. No proceeds of labour must be surrendered
to the capitalist as interest or rent. This is the only condition imposed by the
demand for the right to the common or collective whole proceeds of labour.
The right to the collective whole proceeds of labour does not imply that we
should trouble about the proceeds of labour of the individual worker. For
whatever one worker may fail to secure will be added to the remuneration of
another worker. The apportioning of the workers' shares follows, as hitherto,
the laws of competition, competition being keener, and the personal proceeds of
labour being less, the easier and simpler the work. The workers who perform the
most highly qualified work are most securely withdrawn from the competition of
the masses, and are therefore able to obtain the highest price for the product
of their labour. In certain cases some natural physical aptitude (such as
singing, for example) may take the place of intelligence in eliminating the
competition of the masses. Fortunate is he whose service liberates him from the
dread of competition.
The realisation of the right to the whole proceeds of labour will benefit all
individual workers in the form of an addition to the present proceeds of their
labour, which may be doubled or trebled, but will not be levelled. Levelling the
proceeds of labour is an aim of communism. Our aim, on the contrary, is the
right to the whole proceeds of labour as apportioned by competition. As an
accompanying effect of the reforms necessary to ensure the right to the whole
common proceeds of labour, we may, indeed, expect the existing differences in
the individual proceeds of labour which are sometimes, particularly in commerce,
very great, to be reduced to more reasonable proportions; but that is only an
accompanying effect. The right to the whole proceeds of labour, in our sense,
does not imply any such levelling. Industrious, capable and efficient workers
will, therefore, always secure larger proceeds of labour, proportionate to their
higher efficiency. To this will be added the rise of wages in consequence of the
disappearance of unearned income.
Summary
The product of labour, the yield of labour and the proceeds labour are not
immediately comparable. There is no common measure for these quantities. The
conversion of one into the other is not done by measuring but by contract, by a
bargain.
It is impossible to say whether the proceeds of labour of in workers do or do
not correspond to the whole proceeds of their labour.
The whole proceeds of labour can only be understood to the common or collective
proceeds of labour.
The right to the whole collective proceeds of labour implies the total abolition
of all unearned income, namely interest and rent.
When interest and rent are eliminated from economic life, proof is complete,
that the right to the whole proceeds of labour has been realised, and that the
collective proceeds of labour are equal to the collective product of labour.
The suppression of unearned income raises the individual of labour - doubling or
trebling them. There is no levelling to be expected, or only a partial one.
Differences in the individual product of labour will be accurately translated
into the individual proceeds of labour.
The general laws of competition determining the relative amounts of the
individual proceeds of labour will remain in force. The most efficient worker
will receive the highest proceeds of labour, to use as he pleases.
Today the proceeds of labour are curtailed by rent and interest, which are not,
of course, determined arbitrarily, but by the conditions of the market, everyone
taking as much as the conditions of the market allow him.
We shall now examine the manner in which these market conditions are created,
beginning with rent on land.
A landowner has the choice of cultivating his land or
allowing it to lie fallow. His possession of the land is independent of its
cultivation. Land does not suffer from lying fallow; on the contrary, it
improves; indeed, under certain systems of cultivation, to let the soil lie
fallow is the only method of restoring its fertility.
A landowner, therefore, has no inducement to allow others to use his property (farm,
building-site, oil or coal field, water-power, forest and so forth) without
compensation. If the landowner is offered no compensation, no rent, for its use,
he simply lets his land lie fallow. He is absolute master of his property.
Anyone needing land and applying to a landowner will obviously, therefore, have
to make a disbursement called rent. Even if we could multiply the surface of the
earth and its fertility, it would never occur to a landowner to let others use
his land free of charge. If the worst came to the worst he might turn his
property into a hunting ground or use it as a park. Rent is an inevitable
condition of every tenancy, because the pressure of competition in the supply of
land for letting can never be great enough to make the use of land gratuitous.
How much, then, will the landowner be able to demand ? If the whole surface of
the earth were needed for the sustenance of mankind; if no more free land were
obtainable far or near; if the whole surface of the earth were in private
possession and under cultivation, and if the employment of more labour, the
application of so-called intensive cultivation, resulted in no increase of
produce; then the dependence of those without property on their landlords would
be as absolute as it was at the time of serfdom, and accordingly the landlords
would raise their claims to the utmost limit of the attainable; they would claim
for themselves the entire produce of labour, the entire harvest, and grant to
the labourer, as to a common slave, only what sufficed for his subsistence and
propagation. Under such conditions the so-called " iron law of wages "
would hold good. Cultivators of the soil would be at the mercy of landowners,
and rent would be equal to the yield of the land, less the cost of feeding the
cultivator and his draught animals, and less capital-interest.
The conditions which would result in an "iron wage" do not, however,
exist; for the earth is much larger and more fertile than is necessary for the
support of its present population. Even with present-day extensive cultivation,
hardly one-third of its area is exploited, the remainder lying fallow or being
unclaimed. If instead of extensive cultivation, intensive cultivation were
generally introduced - one-tenth of the surface of the earth would perhaps
suffice to provide mankind with the average amount of foodstuffs consumed by the
workers at the present day. Nine-tenths of the earth's surface in this case, be
left fallow. (Which, of course, does not mean that mankind would be satisfied
with such a result. If everyone desired to eat his fill of something better than
potatoes; if everyone wanted to have a saddle-horse, a court-yard with peacocks
and pigeons, or a rose garden and a swimming-pool the earth might, even with
intensive cultivation, be too small).
Intensive cultivation comprises: drainage of swamps, irrigation, mixture of
soils, deep ploughing, blasting of rocks, marling, application of fertilisers;
choice of plants for culture, improvements of plants and animals; destruction of
pests in orchards and vineyards, destruction of locusts; saving of draught
animals through railway, canal and motor transport; more economical use of
foodstuffs and fodder through exchange; limitation of sheep-breeding through the
cultivation of cotton; vegetarianism and so forth. Intensive cultivation
requires much labour, extensive cultivation much land.
No one, then, is at present compelled, by complete lack of land, to appeal to
the landowners, and because this compulsion does not exist (but solely for this
reason) the dependence of those without land on the landowners is limited. But
the landowners are in possession of the best land, and it would require a great
deal of labour to bring into cultivation the only unclaimed land in settled
neighbourhoods. Intensive cultivation, again, involves considerably more trouble,
and not everyone is capable of emigrating and settling in the unclaimed lands of
the wilderness; apart from the fact that emigration costs money, and that the
produce of those lands can be brought to market only at great expense in
transport-costs and import-duties.
The farmer knows all this, and the landowner likewise. So before the farmer
makes up his mind to emigrate; before he sets about draining the neighbouring
swamp; before he turns to market gardening, he will ask the landowner what rent
he demands for his field. And before answering the question the landowner will
think the matter over and calculate the difference between the proceeds of
labour on his field and the proceeds of labour (* We again call attention to the
difference between the product of labour and the proceeds of labour. The product
of labour of the emigrant may be ten times larger, yet the proceeds of his
labour the same.) on waste land, garden land, or unclaimed land in Africa,
America, Asia, or Australia. For the landowner is determined to obtain this
difference for himself; this is what he can claim as for his field. As a general
rule, however, there is not much calculation. In these matters both parties are
guided by experience. Some hardy young fellow emigrates and, if he reports
favourably, others follow. In this way the supply of labour at home is reduced,
the consequence being a general rise of wages. If emigration continues, wages
will rise to a point at which the would-be emigrant becomes doubtful whether he
had not better stay at home. This indicates that the proceeds of labour at home
and in the new country are again equal. Sometimes an emigrant makes an estimate
beforehand. So it may be worth while examining such a calculation.
An Emigrant's Estimate
Travelling expenses for himself and family $1000
Accident and life insurance during the voyage 200
Health insurance for acclimatisation, that is, the slim which an insurance
company would charge for the special risk due to the change of climate 200
Prospecting and fencing 600
We may assume that the same amount of working capital is required as in Germany,
so it is not included in the estimate
Cost of emigrating and settling $2000
-----
These expenses, which the farmer in Germany does not incur, are added to the
working capital. the interest on which is charged to working costs: 5% on $2000
$100
We assume that the settler, with the same amount of the same amount as on his
native competition of which is here to be considered. We remember that the
farmer, like any other producer, in the products of his labour but only in the
goods for consumption which he can obtain for that is, in the proceeds of his
labour. The settler must send his products to market and convert the money he
obtains for them into the goods he needs for consumption. And he must pay for
the conveyance of these goods to his new home. The market for the exchange of
his products is, as a rule, distant; if we suppose it to be Germany, a country
which is forced to import large quantities of agricultural produce, the emigrant
will have to pay:
Freight-charges for cart, railway, ship and lighter 200
Import-duty in Germany 400
Freight-charges for fighter, ship, railway and cart for the goods received in
exchange 200
Import-duty in the new country 100
-----
$1000
In the above estimate the conversion of the product of labour into the proceeds
of labour, usually effected by way of commerce, the emigrant for freight,
customs-duties and commercial profit the sum of $1000, an expense which the
cultivator of German soil avoids. If, therefore, the latter pays $1000 in rent
for a piece of land which yields the same product of labour as the emigrant's
homestead, the proceeds of his labour are equal to those of the emigrant.
There is the same economic difference in favour of the above piece of land when
compared with waste land brought under cultivation in Germany, but here instead
of transport costs and customs-duties, we have to enter the interest on the
capital employed for reclaiming the land (drainage of a swamp, mixture of the
different layers of soil, liming and manuring). In the case of intensive
cultivation the difference consists, not of interest and freight, but of the
cost of cultivation.
Rent, then, tends to reduce the proceeds (not the produce) of labour to the same
general level everywhere. Whatever agricultural advantages well-cultivated
German farm land possesses over the Luneburg Heath or, through its proximity to
the markets, over unappropriated land in Canada, are claimed by landlords as
rent, or appear, if the land is sold, as its price, which is simply the rent
capitalised. All differences in land as regards fertility, climate, access to
the markets, customs-duties, freights and so forth are levelled by rent. (It
should be noted that in this connection wages are not mentioned; the omission is
intentional).
Economically speaking, rent on land reduces the globe for the farmer,
manufacturer and capitalist (if he is not a landowner), to a perfectly uniform
surface. As Flürscheim puts it: "Just as the inequalities of the ocean bed
are transformed into a level surface by the water, so inequalities of land are
levelled by rent". It is a remarkable fact that rent reduces the proceeds
of labour of all cultivators of the soil to the yield which may be expected from
unreclaimed land at home, or from unclaimed land in the far-off wilderness. The
notions of fertile, barren, loamy, sandy, swampy, rich, poor, well or badly
situated, are rendered, economically speaking, meaningless by rent on land. Rent
makes it a matter of indifference to a man whether he cultivates moorland in the
Eiffel, or a market-garden at Berlin, or a vineyard on the Rhine.
The proceeds of labour on freeland, waste-land, marsh and
moor determine how much the landowner must pay as wages or how much he can claim
as rent. The farm-labourer will obviously claim a wage equal to the proceeds of
labour on freeland, since he is free to take possession of and cultivate
freeland (which term we shall soon define more closely). Nor is it necessary for
every farm-labourer to threaten to emigrate when negotiating about his wages.
Married men with many children, for instance, would gain nothing by such a
threat, since the landowner knows that it cannot be carried into effect. But it
suffices if the emigration of the younger men causes a general shortage of
labour. Even although many labourers are unable to emigrate, the shortage of
labour caused by the emigration of others supports them in their negotiations
about wages as effectively as if they had already booked their passage.
(*How greatly wages are influenced by emigrants and migrating labour is
illustrated by the following passage from a speech by President Wilson on May
20th, 1918: " When the American Secretary of Defence was in Italy, a member
of the Italian Government enumerated to him the various reasons why Italy felt
intimately connected with the United States. The Italian Minister remarked: -
'If you wish to make an interesting experiment go into any troop-train and ask
the soldiers in English which of them have been in America. The rest you will
see for yourself.'
Our Secretary of Defence did board a troop-train and asked the men how many of
them had been in America. It seems that more than half of them rose to their
feet."
The Italian receivers of rent had driven these men to America, and the American
receivers of rent had driven them home again. Because they fared as badly in
America as they had fared at home, the poor devils kept restlessly wandering to
and from.
Wilson added: "There are American hearts in this Italian army!" But we
know better; when these migrating workers left their country they cursed their
fate, and they cursed their fate when they left America.)
On the other hand the tenant farmer must be allowed to keep for himself an
amount equal to the proceeds of labour of the freeland emigrant and the
farm-labourer, after deduction of farm-rent and the interest on his working
capital. Thus farm-rent also, is determined by the proceeds of labour on
freeland. The landowner when calculating the rent of a farm need not leave the
tenant a margin greater than the proceeds of labour on freeland, and the tenant
is not compelled to accept less.
If the proceeds of labour on freeland fluctuate, the fluctuation is transferred
to wages and to farm-rent.
Among the circumstances influencing the proceeds of labour on freeland we must
consider, in the first place, the distance between the unappropriated land and
the place where the products are consumed. We may suppose this to be the place
where the commodities taken in exchange are made (manufacturing centre) or
collected (trading centre). The importance of the distance from the market is
best seen from the difference in the price of a field in the vicinity of the
town and an equally fertile field farther from the market. The reason for the
difference in price is simply the distance from the market.
In the Canadian wheat district, for example, where to this day good land can be
obtained free by everyone, the wheat has to be carried on wagons, along unbeaten
tracks, to the far-distant railroad by which it is conveyed to Duluth to be
shipped on lake steamers. These carry the wheat to Montreal, where it is
transferred to ocean steamers. From there the voyage continues to Europe, say to
Rotterdam, where another transfer to the Rhine vessels is necessary. These go as
far as Mannheim, and to reach the markets of Strasbourg, Stuttgart or Zürich,
the wheat must here be loaded on railway trucks. And its price in these markets,
after payment of import-duties, must be the same as the price of wheat grown on
the spot. It is a long journey costing a great deal of money; yet the balance of
the market price that remains after deducting import-duties, freight, insurance,
brokerage, stamp-duties, interest on money advanced, sacks, etc. is still only
the sum obtained by the sale of the product of labour, and not what is required
by the settler in the wilderness of Saskatchewan. This sum has to be transformed
into articles for use - salt, sugar, cloth, fire-arms, tools, books, coffee,
furniture, etc. and it is only when all these objects have arrived at the
settler's homestead, and the freight on them has been paid, that he can say:
"These are the proceeds of my labour plus interest on my capital." (Whether
the settler has borrowed the money necessary for emigration or is working with
his own capital, he is bound to deduct interest on his capital from the product
of his labour).
It is obvious, therefore, that the proceeds of labour on such freeland must
depend to a great extent on transport costs. These costs have been steadily
sinking, as is shown by the following table: (Taken from Mulhall's Dictionary of
Statistics).
Freight-rates for one ton of grain from Chicago to Liverpool:-
1873 - $17
1880 - 10
1884 - 6
That is, from Chicago to Liverpool alone, a saving of $11 on freight for every
ton of wheat; almost one sixth of the price in 1884, or one fourth of the
present price (1911). But the distance from Chicago to Liverpool is only part of
the distance from Saskatchewan to Mannheim; hence the $11 are only part of the
actual saving on transport costs.
There is the same saving of freight on the goods consumed by the settler. The
grain was the product of labour; the price, $63 in 1884, of a ton of wheat was
the yield of labour; and the return shipment comprised the objects of the
proceeds of labour, to obtain which the settler produced the wheat. For we must
keep in mind that the industrial workers in Germany who eat Canadian wheat, must
always pay for it with their own products which they send directly or indirectly
to Canada and for which, therefore, freight has likewise to be paid. Thus the
saving on cheaper freight is doubled, and the proceeds of labour on freeland,
which determine the general wage in Germany, are augmented.
But it must not be supposed that the saving of a certain sum on freight is
translated into an exactly corresponding increase in the proceeds of labour of
the settler. In reality the proceeds of his labour will increase by only about
half the saving on freight; and the reason for this is that the rising proceeds
of labour of the settler on freeland raise the wages of the agricultural workers
in Germany. The rising wages of farm labourers and of settlers on freeland cause
industrial workers to pass over to these pursuits. The relation existing between
the production of agricultural and of industrial goods is modified, and in
consequence their exchange ratio is also modified. The settler has to pay higher
prices for the objects of the proceeds of his labour (industrial products). The
quantity of these industrial products does not, therefore, increase in
proportion to the increased yield of labour of the settler on freeland resulting
from lower transport costs. The difference, according to the laws of competition,
falls to the industrial workers. What happens here is what happens when improved
technical methods, such as steam-power, reduce the cost of production. The
producer and the consumer share the gain.
Here again it may be worth while to illustrate by means of figures the influence
of a change of transport costs on the proceeds of labour of the settler on
freeland, and consequently on rent and wages.
I. The proceeds of labour of a settler on freeland in Canada with a freight-rate
of $17 per ton in the year 1873.
Product of labour: 10 tons of wheat shipped to Mannheim and there sold at $63
per ton $630
Less 10 times $17 for freight, etc. 170
Yield of labour ... $460
This money-yield of labour is spent in Germany for the purchase of goods for use
which, when shipped to Canada cause the same expense for packing, freight,
import-duties, deterioration, etc. as the wheat on its voyage to Germany 170
The proceeds of labour of the settler therefore amount to $290
II. The same calculation in the year 1884 with a freight-rate of $6 per ton.
Product of labour: 10 tons of wheat at $63 per ton $630
Less 10 times $6 for freight 60
Yield of labour $570
This yield of labour, which is $110 greater than in the first calculation, is
now converted into the proceeds of labour, that is, into industrial products.
For the reasons indicated above, the ratio of exchange between industrial and
agricultural products has been modified in favour of industry. Let us suppose
that this rise in the price of industrial commodities absorbs half the increased
money-yield of labour, that is 55
$515
From this we have to deduct the return freight which we must put a little higher,
as the amount of the goods has increased by the amount economised on freight;
instead of $60 freight amounts to 61
The proceeds of labour of the settler now therefore amount to $454
Thus the decrease in freight has raised the proceeds of labour of the settler on
freeland from $290 to $454, so the wages demanded by the German farm labourer
will automatically increase by the same amount, and tenant farmers will claim a
correspondingly larger share of the product of labour for themselves. And rent
on land will decrease in the same ratio.
If in Germany in 1873 the price of 10 tons of wheat was $630
And the wages for producing it amounted to $290
Then 10 tons of land (* A ton of land: a Danish land-measure denoting the amount
of land that produces one ton of grain. A ton of land therefore indicates an
area of land which varies according to the quality of the soil.) brought the
landowner who worked or let them, rent amounting to $340
But if in 1884 wages rise to $454, the rent must fall to $176
(that is $340, less $164 increase of wages).
What the settler on freeland has to pay in freight is therefore deducted from
the proceeds of his labour; and the landowner in Germany may demand this amount
as farm-rent if he lets his land, or deduct it as rent from the product of his
farm-labourers if he works his land himself. In other words, what the freeland
settler pays as freight is pocketed by the landowner as rent.
Rail and shipping costs are not of course the only factor
influencing the proceeds of labour of the settler on freeland, and consequently
the wages of the German farm-labourer. Man does not live by bread alone, so the
proceeds of labour are not the sole cause of his decision for or against
emigration. The national aid social life of the country which the emigrant is to
leave, and of the country he is going to, have often a strong and determining
influence, and many a man is satisfied with smaller proceeds of labour at home,
finding compensation for the loss in the possession of a laurel wreath for
rabbit-breeding or in the song of the chaffinches, which in his opinion is
nowhere so beautiful as in the home country. These attractive or repelling
forces fluctuate, sometimes stimulating and sometimes restraining emigration.
Many German farmers, for instance, are again emigrating from Russia, not in hope
of higher proceeds of labour, but because conditions there are no longer quite
to their taste. All these factors counteract to some extent the forces tending
to level the purely material proceeds of labour of the emigrant and of the
farm-labourer left behind. Let us suppose, for example, that we resolve to
render life pleasanter for German workers, the means to be derived from the
prohibition of alcoholic drink. Prohibition itself would enrich the lives of the
workers, and especially those of their wives; and the millions which alcohol
directly and indirectly costs the people might be employed for an effective
endowment of motherhood in the shape of a monthly State subsidy to cover the
expense of bringing up each child. Or for better schools, for public
reading-rooms, theatres or churches, or free treats at pastry shops, popular
festivals, assembly-rooms etc. The question whether a man was going to emigrate
would not then be settled solely by an estimate of the material proceeds of his
labour; many wives would induce their husbands to stay, and many emigrants would
return. The effect on wages and rent is obvious. The landowners would raise
their demands until the restraining influence of prohibition on the would-be
emigrant had been compensated. The cakes given gratis to the women in the
national pastry shops would be abstracted from their husband's wages in the form
of an increase of rent.
Thus every advantage which Germany offers for professional, intellectual and
social life is confiscated by rent on land. Rent is poetry, science, art and
religion capitalised. Rent converts everything into hard cash: Cologne Cathedral,
the brooks of the Eiffel, the twitter of birds among the beech-leaves. Rent
levies a toll on Thomas à Kempis, on the relics at Kevelaar, on Goethe and
Schiller, on the incorruptibility of our officials, on our dreams for a happier
future, in a word, on anything and everything; a toll which it forces up to the
point at which the worker asks himself: Shall I remain and pay - or shall I
emigrate and renounce it all ? The workers are always at the gold-point. (In
foreign trade the gold-point is that state in the balance of payments at which
merchants are uncertain whether it is more profitable to pay in bills of
exchange or in gold. The cost of transportating gold is the billbroker's "rent".)
The more pleased a man is with his country and his fellow citizens, the higher
the price charged by the landlord for this pleasure. The tears of the departing
emigrant are pearls of great price for the landlord. For this reason city
landlords often organise improvement societies and other institutions intended
to render town life attractive, in order to restrain departure and stimulate
arrival and so to raise the rents on their building sites. Homesickness is the
tap-root of rent on land.
But if the German farm labourer does not live by bread alone, neither does the
settler on freeland. The material proceeds of labour are only part of what man
needs to make life worth living. The emigrant had to struggle to overcome the
emotional forces binding him to his native land, and similarly in his new home
he finds many things to attract or to repel him. The attractions tend to make
the proceeds of labour appear sufficient to him (just as everyone is prepared to
do agreeable work for a smaller remuneration), whereas the repellent features
diminish them. If the repellent circumstances preponderate (climate, insecurity
of life and property, vermin and so forth) the proceeds of labour must be
correspondingly larger, if the emigrant is to stay on and encourage those who
remained at home to follow his example. Everything that influences the life and
happiness of the settler on freeland has a direct influence on the contentment
of the German worker and affects his wage demands. This influence begins with
the account of the journey. If the voyage passed off without sea-sickness, if
life on board and the food were tolerable, those left behind will be encouraged.
If the settler tells of liberty he is enjoying, of hunting and riding, of great
hauls of salmon and herds of buffaloes, of his right of disposing freely of the
riches of nature, of his being treated everywhere as a free citizen and not as a
serf and beggar, the labourer at home will of course hold his head higher during
the wage negotiations than if his brother writes of the inroads of Red Indians,
of rattlesnakes, vermin and hard work.
All this is known to the landowners, so if a letter of lament arrives, the most
is made of it; it is published in the Press which is given to understand that it
must on the other hand carefully exclude any reports that might prove attractive
and encouraging. The organisation which is set up to advertise the attractions
of the home country is also entrusted with the task of reviling freeland. Every
snake-bite, every scalp taken, every swarm of locusts, every shipwreck, by
making the workers less likely to emigrate and more amenable, is converted into
hard cash for the landowners.
When freeland is spoken of we first think of the vast tracts
of uncultivated land in North and South America. This freeland is easily and
comparatively cheaply reached. The climate is suitable for Europeans, the social
conditions are to many people attractive; the security of life and property is
fair. On his arrival the immigrant is accommodated for a week or two in a hostel
for immigrants at the expense of the State, and in some countries he is given a
free railway ticket to the farthest limit of settled land. Here he is free to
settle immediately. He may pick out the site he likes best: pasture, ploughland
or forest. The homestead that he has a right to claim is extensive enough to
provide work for the largest family. As soon as the settler has driven in the
boundary stakes and notified the land-office, he may start work. Nobody
interferes with him or even inquires who allowed him to till the earth and reap
the fruits of his industry. He is lord of the land between his four stakes.
Land of this kind we call freeland of the first class. Such freeland is not of
course to be found in settled parts, but only where men are few and far between.
Within the tracts already occupied there are, however, large areas that are not
cultivated, but which by some abuse of State-power have become the private
property of individuals living in some far-off place. A few thousand persons
living in Europe own between them hundreds of millions of acres of such land
situated in America, Africa, Australia and Asia. Anyone wishing to occupy a
piece of this land has to come to terms with the proprietors, but as a rule he
may buy or rent what he desires for a nominal sum. Whether he does or does not
pay a few pence an acre annually for the land he intends to cultivate can make
no appreciable difference in the proceeds of his labour. Such conditionally
freeland we call freeland of the second class.
Freeland of the first and the second classes is still to be found in abundance
in every part of the world outside Europe. It is not always land of the best
quality. Much of it is densely overgrown with forests needing a great deal of
labour to clear. Large areas suffer from lack of water and can be made fertile
only by expensive irrigation schemes. Other land again, often of the best
quality, has to be drained; or being situated in remote valleys lacks means of
communication without which exchange of the produce is impossible. Freeland of
this kind can be taken up only by emigrants possessing capital or credit. For
the theory of rent and of wages, however, it does not matter whether this
freeland is brought under cultivation by a company of capitalists or by the
emigrants directly. The distinction only affects capital and its interests. If
the emigrant settles on land which has been opened up in this way, that is, with
the help of capital, he has to pay the customary interest on the capital
invested, and he must add this interest to his working expenses.
For individuals or companies themselves possessing the means necessary for
land-reclamation on a larger scale half the world is still freeland. The best
land in California and along the Rocky Mountains was until lately a desert; now
it is a vast garden. The British have made Egypt habitable for millions of men
by means of the Nile dams. The Zuider-Zee and many deserts such as Mesopotamia
will also be brought into cultivation again by a similar expenditure of capital.
Thus we may say that freeland of the second class will be at the disposal of
mankind for an indefinite period to come.
The most important freeland, however, and that which is also
of greatest significance for the theory of rent and wages is freeland of the
third class, which is everywhere available close at hand. The conception of this
freeland, however, is not so simple as that of the other two forms and calls for
some reflection.
A few examples will serve to make the matter clear to everyone.
Example 1. In Berlin the building regulations do not allow houses to be built
more than four storeys high. If the limit were two storeys the city would have
to cover twice its present area to lodge the same population. Hence the land
saved by the third and fourth storeys is to this day unoccupied building land.
If the American manner of building were permitted in Berlin - that is, 40
storeys instead of four - one-tenth of the present building area of Berlin would
suffice. The rest would form a surplus and would be offered to any builder at
little more than the price of a potato patch. Freeland for building purposes is,
therefore, available even in the centre of any large German city, in an
unlimited quantity - from the fourth storey upwards towards the clouds.
Example 2. In the republic of "Agraria" the use of chemical
fertilisers is prohibited by law, nominally because it is alleged to be
injurious to health, in reality in order to limit the output of grain and so to
keep up its price. The landowners of Agraria believe that little and dear is
better for them than much and cheap. In consequence of this prohibition and the
resulting small crops and high prices, and because emigration, also, is
prohibited, the people of Agraria have brought all wastes, swamps and moors
under cultivation, and so contrived to make the crops meet the needs of the
population. But in spite of this the people are discontented and clamour for
repeal of the prohibition, it being generally expected that the use of chemical
fertilisers would treble the produce of the soil, as it did in Germany.
What would be the result of repeal on rent and wages ? Would not the same thing
happen in Agraria that happens in the city, when new building regulations allow
the number of storeys to be trebled ? With the use of chemical fertilisers the
soil of the republic would suddenly yield trebled harvests, harvests three times
larger than the present population requires. The consequence would be that of
every three acres two would be allowed to lie fallow at the disposal of future
generations. In a republic where every inch of soil, every swamp is cultivated,
the import of chemical fertilisers would suddenly create vast areas of freeland.
And this freeland would, for the time being, be used only for hunting and would
be leased for this purpose, for a nominal amount.
These examples from the building industry and agriculture show how new land,
freeland of the third class, may be created and is being daily created as the
result of scientific discovery. The nomad requires 100 acres to provide for his
family, the farmer 10, the gardener one or less.
The whole agricultural area of Europe is as yet cultivated so superficially, and
population, even in Germany, is still so sparse, that if garden culture were
generally adopted, half the area at present under cultivation would have to be
left fallow, first because we should lack purchasers for such quantities of
foodstuffs, and secondly because we should lack the workers necessary for such
an intensive cultivation of the soil.
We may therefore consider the whole of Germany as such freeland of the third
class. With regard to the yield of the soil which the farmer working intensively
reaps over and above the yield of the hunter, the nomad, and the farmer working
extensively, all farm land may be considered as freeland, just as Americans may
consider the space above the storeys already in existence, up to the clouds, as
free building land.
Let us apply these examples to the theory of rent and wages. Germany, in the
limited sense above described, is still freeland, and the farm-labourer may at
any time take refuge on this freeland if dissatisfied with his wages. The wages
of farm-labourers cannot fall permanently below the proceeds of labour on such
freeland of the third class, any more than they can fall below the proceeds of
labour on freeland of the first class. Here, then, is an unfailing support for
the farm-labourer in his wage negotiations.
And now, how much can the labourer demand as wages ? How much the landowner as
rent ?
Let us suppose that, with the usual extensive farming methods
of the district, 12 men are needed to cultivate 100 acres of land, and that the
harvest amounts to 600 tons, that is, 50 tons for every man and 6 tons per acre.
Let us further suppose that with intensive farming the same area requires 50 men
to cultivate and yields 2000 tons, or 40 tons instead of 50 for each worker, and
20 instead of 6 tons per acre.
Thus the produce of intensive cultivation is augmented as compared to the area,
but diminished as compared to the work.
With extensive cultivation:
Twelve men produce 50 tons each, that is 600 tons.
With intensive cultivation:
Twelve men produce 40 tons each, that is 480 tons.
So the difference of 120 tons is to be attributed to the larger area of 100
acres, which enabled these 12 men to adopt this extensive cultivation, that is,
cultivation requiring less labour. They will of course prefer this method as
long as the land necessary for it is at their disposal. But if the land is not
at their disposal they are forced to have recourse to intensive cultivation and
to be satisfied with the smaller product of labour. The disadvantage is so great
that if anybody places the area necessary for extensive cultivation at their
disposal they will consent to pay for the advantage resulting for them, or, in
other words, the owner of this area will be able to levy an additional rent
corresponding to the difference between the product of labour in extensive and
intensive cultivation, the former being larger, as is proved by experience. In
our example, then, the rent of 100 acres of land will be 120 tons.
Agriculture tends to extensive cultivation to save labour, but to intensive
cultivation to save land. Out of the tension thus arising rent is born, and the
degree of this tension (a matter of experience) determines the distribution of
the farm produce between rent and wages.
We need not stop here to explain why extensive cultivation yields more produce
for a given amount of labour and less produce for a given amount of land. That
is a question of agricultural technique. For us it suffices to know that such is
the case in agriculture, that it is founded in the nature of things. If it were
otherwise, if extensive cultivation yielded 40 tons while intensive cultivation
yielded 50 tons a head, the whole of agriculture would tend towards intensive
cultivation. All the land that could not he stocked with labour would be left
fallow, simply because any workers still available would reap larger harvests by
a still more intensive tillage of the land already under cultivation than by
cultivating fallow land.
(The theory of population which asserts that population corresponds to the food
supply, is not inconsistent with the above proposition. Population grows with
the augmentation of the food supply; it follows in the wake of intensive
cultivation, it does not precede it.)
By extensive cultivation we mean that form of agriculture in which all the
labour offering itself must be employed in order to cultivate the whole of the
area available, no matter what the method of cultivation may be, hunting, cattle
grazing, three-field system, marsh culture, or present-day comparatively
well-developed farming.
By intensive cultivation we mean that form of agriculture which, if carried on
on a large scale, must result in a general shortage of labour.
Intensive and extensive cultivation are therefore relative terms. The herdsman
is an intensive worker as compared to the huntsman. Hence pastoral tribes must
generally pay rent for the use of their land (hunting-grounds), and are able to
do so.
Extensive cultivation yields the larger product of labour (wages and rent),
whereas intensive cultivation yields the larger crop. The landowner would like
to combine the two, and of course endeavours to practice intensive cultivation.
He cannot, however, do so without withdrawing labour from among the extensive
cultivators and so causing land to be left fallow (freeland of the third class).
Now it stands to reason that the owners of this land are unwilling to let it lie
fallow. They therefore try to attract labour to it by raising wages; and in
doing so they are prepared to go close to the limit of profitableness (absorption
of rent in wages), since a landowner will prefer to receive a dollar an acre
rent rather than to receive nothing at all.
Freeland of the third class has thus the function of levelling wages and rent.
Freeland of the third class makes arbitrary fixation of wages impossible. The
landowner does not fix wages as low as he pleases, neither does the labourer
demand as much as he chooses; the amount that falls to each is determined by
economic laws.
Technical improvements increase the product of labour, and if
they increase it equally in intensive and in extensive cultivation, wages and
rent will also increase equally. The ratio of distribution then remains
unchanged, the landlord deriving the same advantage as the workers from
improvement of the means of production.
Technical improvements are rarely, however, of equal benefit to the two modes of
cultivation, extensive and intensive. What, for instance, can the intensive
farmer do with a ten-share motor plough, or with a seed distributor ? Such
machines can be used only for large areas; for intensive cultivation they are
useless, just as lions are useless for catching mice.
For freeland of the third class the motor plough is quite useless, its realm
being freeland of the first or second class, the vast plains of America, where a
single motor plough (* The motor plough is sometimes the property of the
agricultural co-operative society, but as a general rule it belongs to a
contractor, the local blacksmith, who also keeps it in repair.) will plough the
fields of 50 or more farmers, and plough them well and cheaply. The product of
labour of these freeland-settlers is of course thereby increased enormously. But
on the product of labour depend the proceeds of labour, and the proceeds of
labour of the freeland-settler determine the wages of labour on rented land
everywhere.
Now if all the circumstances connected with conversion of the product of labour
into the proceeds of labour remained unchanged, wages in general would
necessarily rise in the same proportion as the increase in the products of
labour due to the motor plough. These circumstances do not, however, remain
unchanged, and here again we see how necessary it was to distinguish from the
outset, between the product of labour and the proceeds of labour. For it is the
proceeds, and not the product of labour, that determine wages in general.
If the proceeds of labour of the freeland-settler increase, the immediate
consequence is an increase of the proceeds of labour of industrial workers. If
that were not so, industrial workers would return to agricultural labour on
freeland of the first, second or third class. This rise of wages in industry is
brought about by a modification of the exchange ratio between the products of
the freeland-settler and of industry. Instead of 10 sacks of wheat the settler
has to give 12 for a gramophone, a rifle, a medicine-chest. In this way the
settler, when transforming the product of his labour into the proceeds of labour,
has to surrender part of his surplus product to the industrial worker. Thus the
motor plough forces up wages all round.
What the wage-earners gain by the motor plough is, however, more than the
surplus of products created by the plough. The motor plough may produce a
surplus of 100 million tons, but this, if distributed among all the workers,
would be a trifling sum, out of proportion to the increase of the
labour-proceeds of the freeland-settler. The reason why the wage-earners gain
more is as follows:
If there is a rise in the labour-proceeds of the freeland-settler of the first
or second class, the wages of the workers on rented land in Europe rise likewise,
even although there is no increase in the product of their labour. (The
motor-plough not being employed, or being employed only to a limited extent.)
The increase of wages here takes place at the expense of rent on land; the means
for the rise of wages are derived only in a small part from the surplus produce
of the freeland-settler.
We continue our examination of this situation, in which technical improvements
benefit freeland farmers of the first and second classes, without benefiting
intensive cultivation. We have seen that:
The product of labour of the freeland farmer of the first and second class
increases by, say, 20% through introduction of more efficient agricultural
machinery - after allowance for interest and for upkeep of the machines.
The Proceeds of labour of the freeland farmer increase by only 10% since, as we
have already shown, the industrial worker demands and obtains more for the
product of his labour.
The exchange relation between industrial and agricultural products shifts 10% in
favour of industry. Thus of the 20% increase of the product, only half, or 10%,
is transferred to the general rate of wages.
German landowners must draw on their rents to meet the increased demands of
their labourers, since the product of German land has not increased.
But the landowner's loss is not confined to the decrease of his rent expressed
in tons of agricultural produce - which are of as little use to him as are tons
of agricultural produce to the freeland settler. For with the exchange of his
tons of rent-products for industrial products he again loses, because of the
shift in the ratio of exchange - his total loss being considerably more than
10%.
The smaller the rent in proportion to labour costs, the harder the landowner is
hit by the rise of wages. But since landowners cannot, obviously, engage
labourers at a loss, and since landowners practising extensive cultivation
cannot have a greater profit than their colleagues practising intensive
cultivation, there is a recession from intensive to extensive cultivation. Less
labour is required, labourers are thrown out of employment, and these unemployed
labourers depress wages below their true level, namely the labour-proceeds of
freeland-farmers of the first and second classes (which have risen 10%).
Emigration then increases until equilibrium between wages at home and the
proceeds of labour overseas is re-established.
When technical progress benefits extensive cultivation in the home country,
without benefiting intensive cultivation, the larger share of the increased
product falls to rent. In spite of the increased product, wages may then even
fall below their former level.
Thus technical improvements affect very unequally the distribution of the
products of the soil, much depending upon where the benefit falls, whether on
freeland of the first and second classes, or on freeland of the third class, or
on extensive cultivation.
The workers, in former times, were not always wrong when, to safeguard their
interests, they clamoured for the destruction of machinery. It may happen that
rent not only absorbs the whole of the surplus production from technical
improvements, but also takes away part of the former wages.
Scientific discoveries were an even more powerful factor than
machinery in trebling the yield of German land within the last decades. I shall
only mention briefly the use of potash salts, basic slag, and
nitrogen-collecting plants as manure; the artificial production of nitrogenous
fertilisers, (calcium cyanamide), the prevention and cure of contagious diseases
in plants and animals. (*By electrifying the soil the physicist Lodge obtained
an increase of produce of 30-40%.)
These discoveries have not, however, fertilised all soils equally. By far the
greatest gain from them so far has accrued to the peaty, marshy and sandy soils
previously considered barren. Here the development meant more than trebling the
produce; it meant the creation of new soil, for the sand and moor had not been
previously cultivated at all. In Germany a small fraction of these waste-lands
was formerly cultivated as burnt moor and yielded a scanty crop every fifteen
years to those who were willing to undertake this arduous labour.
(*As lately as 30 years ago, more than half the province of Hanover was covered
with heather. Every 15 years the heather was cut, piled and burnt, the ashes
being spread on the land which was then ploughed and yielded a scanty crop of
rye or buckwheat. The smoke from these fires was often observed at 500 miles
distance from Hanover.)
These lands now yield rich harvests every year. Land which was always naturally
fertile cannot, of course, treble its already rich yield. Such land provides the
manure necessary for its own perennial rejuvenation if, as is the general rule,
tillage is combined with cattle-breeding. That is why artificial fertilisers are
much less important in such cases than when applied to lands naturally barren.
And the influence of artificial fertilisers on the produce of freeland of the
first and second class is still slighter. These virgin lands as a rule require
no manuring at all. The cost of transporting artificial fertilisers to such land
is, moreover, prohibitive.
Thus the effect of scientific discoveries on wages and rent varies according to
the nature of the land to which they are applied. As in the case of machinery,
it is impossible to state generally whether they raise or depress rent or wages.
The influence of legislation on the distribution of the
product of labour among rent-receivers and workers is manifold and far-reaching.
It has often been said that politics consist, in the main, of attacks on wages
and rent, and in the corresponding defensive measures. As a rule action is here
dictated by instinct. The interplay of forces is not fully understood, or if it
is understood it is politic to conceal the truth. The advocates of the measures
proposed with so much passion are not greatly concerned about the scientific
proof of their efficacy. Politics and science are uneasy bedfellows; very often
indeed the aim of politics is to prevent, or at least retard, the recognition of
some scientific discovery. What curious things have been said, for example,
about wheat-duties ! "They protect and encourage agriculture", say
those who pocket the immediate advantages; "they are bread-usury and theft",
say those who become aware of the duty in the smallness of the loaf. "The
duties are paid by the foreigner", say some, to which others retort that
the duties are all borne by the consumers. Thus the wrangle proceeds, as it has
proceeded for fifty years, over a purely human transaction open to all to see;
and still the disputants are none the wiser. It is therefore well worth
investigating the influence of legislation, for example the taxation of land, on
the distribution of the product of labour.
When a merchant orders a shipment of tobacco knowing that at the frontier he
will have to pay a duty of $100 per bale, it will be admitted that the merchant
must be assured of recouping this expenditure, plus the interest on the capital
invested, and plus his own profit, in the price of the tobacco when sold. The
import-duty is, for the merchant, an integral part of the merchandise, and is
entered by him in his inventory on the credit side, just like any other item
such as chests, sacks and bales: -
100 Tons Java tobacco $50000
Freight and import-duty 10000
_______
60000
10% expected profit 6000
_______
Capital $66000
That is how the merchant deals with import-duties. Why cannot our landowner deal
similarly with the sum which the State collects from him in the form of a tax on
land ? It is often asserted that he does so. Landowners themselves will tell you
that they intend to charge every tax, with interest and profit added, to the
tenant, so that in the long run the land-tax will be deducted from the scanty
wages of the farm-labourers. If such is the case, these landowners will argue,
is it not preferable to convert the land-tax at once into a poll-tax, a wage-tax
or an income-tax ? The labourers would then at least save the interest and
profit that the landlord adds to the taxes.
In order to examine this problem more closely it is indispensable to answer a
question raised by Ernst Frankfurth in his illuminating little book on unearned
income, namely: What becomes of the proceeds of the land-tax ? For it surely
cannot be immaterial for the fate of the land-tax whether the State employs the
revenue from it to construct new roads through the landlord's estate, and to
reduce the education rate for the children of his tenants, or, say, to pay an
import premium on foreign grain. If we do not know this we cannot determine who,
ultimately, pays the land-tax. So says Ernst Frankfurth.
There are landowners who do not wait for the State to tax them and with the
proceeds to build the roads necessary for exploitation of their estates. They
construct the roads themselves. The costs form a capital investment, like
clearing, draining, and so forth. The landowners expect advantages from the
roads which will balance the interest on the capital to be invested. If,
nevertheless, it is, as a rule, the State that constructs the roads, while
taxing the landlords for the expenditure, this is simply because the roads
usually cross the land of many owners with conflicting interests and therefore
necessitate powers of expropriation which are exclusively the domain of the
State. But even if the State builds the roads, the land-tax levied for the
purpose is a capital investment, the interest on which the landlord expects to
recover to the last farthing. And this is the real nature of almost every tax.
If the State levies a tax to protect the frontier from the inroads of barbarians,
the landlord saves the amount of this tax from the insurance which would
otherwise be necessary against the invasion of Cossacks and Yankees (Russian and
American wheat! ).
So if the State employs the revenue from the land-taxes for the benefit of the
landlords, these taxes must be looked upon as capital investments. They are the
remuneration of the State for services rendered. The landowner may enter these
taxes where he enters the wages of his labourers. If he leases the land to
tenants he will add the tax to the farm rent, recovering it if the State works
cheaply and well, and even making a profit if the State displays the shrewdness
of a clever contractor.
But what if the State taxes the landowners in order to relieve the tenant or the
labourers, say from the education-rate ? Is it still possible for the landlord
to consider the land-tax as a profitable investment ? Let us suppose that such
is not the case, that the landlord cannot charge the tenant with the amount of
the education-rate saved by the latter nor reduce the wages of the labourers.
Tenant and labourers would then have their labour-proceeds increased by the
amount of the education-rate remitted. But why should the landlord raise the
labour-proceeds of the tenants and labourers? Because he is himself taxed? That
is no reason since the labour-proceeds of the tenant and labourer are determined
by the labour-proceeds on freeland of the first, second and third classes. If
the revenue from the land-tax is employed to benefit the freeland-farmer of the
third class likewise, say also in the shape of a reduction of the education-rate,
then, indeed, the equilibrium between the labour-proceeds of the wage-earners
and tenants and those of the freeland-farmers is not disturbed, and it is
impossible for the landowner to transfer the burden of the land-tax to his
tenants and labourers. Otherwise he says to the tenant: "To the other
advantages which my farm offers you, free education for your children is added.
Rich loamy soil, a healthy climate, a fine view of the lake, a situation close
to the market, free schools - sum total - you have got to pay me $10 an
acre". And to his farm labourer the landowner says: "If you do not
consent to a reduction of wages you may go. Calculate whether with the wages I
offer you, together with free schools for your children, and other social
institutions, you are not as well off as if you decide to cultivate freeland of
the first, second or third class. Think it over before you go".
It is clear that the whole burden of the land-tax is transferable as long as its
yield does not benefit freeland farmers, more particularly those of the third
class. If, on the other hand, the revenue of the land-tax is made to benefit, in
some form or other, intensive cultivation, the increase of the labour-proceeds
of freeland-farmers of the third class is passed on to the farm labourers
engaged in extensive cultivation, and the land-tax, in this case, far from being
transferable, hits farm rents doubly, first by the full amount of the tax and
secondly in the form of higher wages demanded by the farm-labourers.
This shows how right Frankfurth was to enquire first about what is done with the
yield of the tax, and how futile it is to attempt to answer the question as to
whether the burden of the land-tax can be shifted or not, without first
establishing the necessary premises. It also leads us to suspect how often the
measures proposed by social reformers must fail, or have the opposite to the
desired effect. And it shows us how greatly the distribution of the
labour-product is influenced by the power of the State.
By the above reasoning we see that a land-tax levied for the
benefit of freeland-farmers, say in the form of a premium on imported wheat,
would hit rent doubly, first by the amount of the tax, and secondly by the
increased wages of farm labourers. Many readers will now be inclined to suppose
that a protective-duty, being the opposite to an import premium, must raise
rents in a two-fold manner, in the first place directly, by the amount of the
special rise, corresponding to the duty, of prices of farm produce, and in the
second place through depression of wages resulting from reduction of the
labour-proceeds of freeland-farmers of the first and second classes.
Let us see if that is true.
To begin with, let it be understood that a protective tariff differs
fundamentally from other revenue duties and taxes in that the interest of the
landowners in the tariff is much greater than that of the State which levies the
duty. For every 100 millions which the State raises out of the import of wheat,
the landowners will levy 1000 millions (* The exact amount for any country can
be calculated from the ratio of imports to home production.) from the consumers
of bread in the form of higher prices. That is why the thing is called a
protective-duty: it is designed to protect and augment the rents of the
landowners, and to give better security to their mortgages. When import-duties
are purely fiscal, as in the case of tobacco, the tax is imposed not only on the
imported goods but also on those produced in the country. Anyone having more
than one tobacco plant in his garden in Germany must inform the revenue
authorities, and in Spain the culture of tobacco is, or was, prohibited for
fiscal reasons. But if the import-duty on wheat is of secondary importance as
revenue, Frankfurth's query as to the use made of the tax is likewise of
secondary importance for what we have set out to demonstrate. We shall therefore
leave out of account the wheat duties themselves, and concentrate our attention
on the farm rents placed under their protection.
There is nothing arbitrary in the distribution of the product between landowner
and farm worker; everything proceeds according to inherent laws. Any artificial
interference with this distribution must be in accordance with these laws, not
in opposition to them, otherwise it will come to nothing. But even if the
attempted interference does come to nothing, some time is usually required for
the disturbed equilibrium to be restored, and meanwhile the play of forces may
resemble the swing of a pendulum that has been set in motion by a push:
distribution will oscillate for some time between rent and wages until the
former state of matters is re-established.
So if protective-duties for the purpose of raising rents at the expense of wages
are in conflict with the economic laws governing the distribution of the product
between rent and wages, they must either fail entirely or succeed only
temporarily, that is, until the equilibrium of forces disturbed by legislative
interference has been restored.
It is not our purpose to investigate these matters further than to obtain a
general picture of the economic processes resulting from import-duties. If we
wished to arrive at conclusions applicable in all possible circumstances to
individual cases, such as, for example the question as to how much an
import-duty of 33% on wheat would raise the price of a certain estate, we should
be obliged to carry the investigation far beyond the scope of this book.
Our first concern with regard to import-duties is their influence on the
proceeds of labour of freeland-farmers of the first and second classes, on which
farm wages on the tariff-protected land depend Of the proceeds of labour of the
freeland-farmers of the third class, whose product of labour is also protected
by the tariff, we shall speak afterwards.
Freeland-farmers of the first and second class rightly consider import-duties as
a burden, like any other charge which renders the conversion of the product of
their labour into proceeds of labour more expensive. Whether this increased
expense results from higher freights, from higher prices of sacks, from piracy,
from fraud, or from import-duties, makes no difference to them. What the
consumer pays for the product of his labour (wheat) the freeland-farmer
considers as the yield of his labour, and this yield is diminished by
import-duties and freight. The proceeds of his labour are therefore
correspondingly smaller. If the loss caused by freight hitherto amounted to 30%
of the price of his product, this loss may be increased to 50 - 60% by the
tariff.
The freight from the Argentine seaports to Hamburg is usually about $4 a ton. To
this is added the cost of railway transport from the farm to the harbour, which
is more than twice as much; in all, therefore, about $13. The duty in Germany is
$14 a ton. The total is thus $27 in a price of about $60.
The immediate effect of the duties is, therefore, to reduce the proceeds of
labour of the freeland-farmers of the first and second classes, and as these
labour proceeds determine the wages of the workers on tariff-protected land,
there is here, too, a reduction of wages, though at first perhaps only in the
form of increased prices for foodstuffs, in connection with stationary money
wages. The duty, then, allows the landowner to demand higher prices for his
agricultural produce without having to pay out this surplus in the form of
higher wages to his labourers, or in higher prices for industrial products for
his own consumption. For a rise of industrial wages - which would mean a
shifting of the burden of the import-duties from industrial workers - is
impossible, since these wages are, as we have seen, also determined by the
labour-proceeds of freeland-farmers of the first and second classes. Industrial
workers are consequently no more able to shift the burden of the import duties
than are farm-labourers and freeland-farmers of the first and second classes. So
until the reactions to be described later begin to make themselves felt, the
whole amount of the import-duty is a free gift to the landowner. And by
import-duty we mean not only the sums received by the public treasury, but also
the sums levied on the consumer in the form of higher prices paid for native
products in the home markets in consequence of the tariff barrier. This means
that every loaf of bread, every egg, every ham, every potato pays a tribute
which goes into the pockets of the landlords. (If the land is let, the duty is
immediately transferred to the rent; if it is sold, the duty is capitalised,
that is, multiplied by 20 or 25, and added to the usual price.)
The duty, say the politicians, is paid by the foreigner. And that is perfectly
true. For the relatively unimportant sum collected as State revenue at the
frontier is, no doubt, paid by the freeland-farmer settled abroad, from the
proceeds of his labour. But can anyone seriously attempt to make wheat-duties
palatable to the German workman by telling him that it is the freeland-farmer
who pays the amount collected by the State at the frontier ? This is cold
comfort for the German worker whose wages are determined by the proceeds of
labour of the freeland-farmer - cold comfort for the man who must pay out of his
own pocket the higher price of food, increased by German landowners by the full
amount of the tariffs.
The belief, the hope, the bold assertion, that capital-interest win bear part of
the wheat-duties is, as we shall show presently, erroneous. Interest, especially
in the case of new capital seeking investment, cannot be taxed. It is free and
independent of tariffs.
The import-duty will, however, produce certain counter-effects that will slowly
but surely make themselves felt, somewhat as follows: The freeland-farmer in
Manitoba, Manchuria, or Argentina writes to his friend in Berlin: " I lose
in freight and import-duties more than half of what you pay for my wheat in
Berlin, and you also lose in freight and import-duties half or more of what I
pay here for your goods (tools, books, medicines and so forth). If we were
neighbours we should save these costs and both you and I would find the proceeds
of our labour doubled. I cannot convey my fields to where you are, but you can
transfer your workshop, your factory here. Come, then, and I will supply you
with whatever food you may require at half the price you have now to pay, while
you will supply me with your products at half the price I have to pay at present."
This calculation is correct, though the obstacles to the execution of the
proposal are many. Industry can, as a rule, prosper only in centres where there
are many other industries, since almost all branches of industry are to some
extent inter-dependent. The emigration of industries must therefore proceed
gradually; it begins with the trades that are naturally most independent:
brickyards, saw-mills, flour-mills, printing houses, furniture and glass
factories, etc., and at first, of course, it affects only commodities upon which
freight-charges and import-duties are especially high. Nevertheless, the
emigration of individual industries depends on a calculation, and it is
import-duty which, added to freight-charges, very frequently calls for a
decision in favour of emigration. The higher the duty on wheat, the more often
will it pay to pack up tools and re-establish the workshop in the vicinity of
the freeland-farmer. And with every new industry established in the
neighbourhood of the freeland-farmer the proceeds of his labour increase, and
this increase reacts, as we know, on wages in the protected country.
The advantages of the tariff to the landowner are therefore sooner or later
absorbed in rising wages. Landowners who realise this will act accordingly: they
will sell their land before the counter-effects make themselves felt, and leave
their successors to go clamouring to Parliament for relief, when the inevitable
reaction involves agriculture in difficulties. (* "Die Not der
Landwirtschaft": "The plight of agriculture" was the political
slogan of the Prussian protectionists. Here "agriculture" was a
euphemism for rent. It would not be difficult to find an English or American
parallel.) (The reduction of rent in consequence of the rise of wages is
inevitable, although it may not always be expressed in figures. For it may
happen that the development here described may synchronise with one of those
frequently occurring currency inflations caused by gold discoveries or
over-issues of paper-money. Currency inflation such as occurred in the period of
1890 to 1914 restores to the landowner what he loses in rent. But this applies
only to mortgaged landed property, and the landowner has also to reckon with the
reverse possibility, namely a gradual fall of prices, as in the years
1873-1890.)
But the reactions set up by a protective tariff are not confined to the
behaviour of freeland-farmers of the first and second classes. We must also find
out what happens to the freeland-farmer of the third class. The effect on him is
the exact reverse of the effect on freeland-farmers of the first and second
classes, who pay the duty out of their pockets, whereas he is under the
protection of the tariff as regards the products he brings to market after
satisfying his own personal needs. So he participates in the blessings of the
protective tariff, that is, in the looting of consumers. Instead of six marks he
now gets 8 marks for a rabbit, and he sells his honey for 1.35 marks instead of
1.10 marks: in short, he obtains higher prices for everything he sells, without
having to pay higher prices for what he has to buy. That is to say, the
labour-proceeds of the freeland-farmer of the third class increase, whereas the
wage workers complain of a decrease in the proceeds of their labour. Thus the
labour-proceeds of the freeland-farmer of the third class increase in a twofold
manner, absolutely on account of the rise of prices, and relatively in
comparison with the decrease of wages. Nevertheless the labour proceeds of the
freeland-farmer of the third class determine the general rate of wages.
Evidently, therefore, the disproportion cannot long continue. Word goes round
that a rabbit can be sold for eight marks, honey for 1.35 marks, potatoes for 5
marks, and goat's milk for 20 pfennigs, so the wage-earners are up in arms with
demands for increased wages. Pointing to the increased labour-proceeds of the
freeland-farmer of the third class they, too, claim higher wages, threatening to
move to the heath, to the marsh, to the waste, if their demands are not granted.
Hence the wage-increase proceeds from freeland of the third class, as well as
from freeland of the first and second classes, and it continues until it has
completely compensated the effect of the wheat duties.
It must be remembered, further, that the special rise of prices of all farm
produce, brought about by the import-duties, and the consequent increase of
rents, must call for new efforts in the direction of intensive cultivation, and
that if the duty raises the labour-proceeds of intensive farmers, wages, and
through them rent, must be still further affected.
The effect of the tariff is to raise the gross proceeds of intensive farmers
and, as the tariff does not at first affect the prices of industrial products,
to increase also the net proceeds of their labour.
But if the labour-proceeds of intensive farmers increase, wages must also rise,
for the labour-proceeds of intensive farmers determine wages in general.
The general conclusion of our examination is consequently that a protective
tariff, through its influence on the proceeds of labour of the freeland-farmer,
is bound sooner or later to counteract itself; so that the protection obtained
can never be other than temporary.
For those who have to pay the tariff charges "temporarily", it may be
a consolation, and for those who enjoy the advantages of the tariff it may be
disquieting, to become aware of their transitory nature. But it is a very
serious matter if the transitory rise of the rent is accepted as permanent by
the farmer when buying land or dividing an inheritance. For what does the farmer
know of theories of rent and wages ? He is guided simply by experience. He sees
the harvest, he knows the prices of farm produce and the wages paid
farm-labourers - his calculation is finished and the bargain luck. The customary
sum is paid in ready money, and the rest is covered by a mortgage. But this
mortgage is not a temporary matter: it is sure to outlast the transient effect
of the tariff upon wages, and it does not decrease when the labourers,
regardless of the stationary selling prices of farm produce approach the farmer
with demands for increased wages. The farmer then begins to complain, once more,
about the plight of agriculture".
If the landowner is able to squeeze $1000 rent out of his
land, he will not be satisfied with less than this amount if he chooses to hire
labourers and to farm the land himself. If the land, after deducting cost of
wages, did not yield at least $1000, the landowner would dismiss the labourers
and let it for $1000.
In no circumstances, therefore, will a day-labourer earn higher proceeds of
labour than the tenant or the settler on unclaimed land; for otherwise the
tenant (or settler) would prefer to work as a day-labourer.
On the other hand the day-labourer will not consent to work for a wage which is
less than what he might earn as a tenant or settler, for otherwise he would rent
a piece of land or emigrate. It is true that he often lacks the money necessary
to run a farm or to emigrate; but whether he has the money or is forced to
borrow it, he must charge interest on it in his calculation, and deduct this
interest from the product of his labour. For it is only what is left to the
settler after paying the interest on his capital that belongs to him as a worker.
If the gross proceeds of the labour of the settler on freeland are $250 and the
interest on his working capital is $50 then the net proceeds of his labour are
$200 and the general rate of wages must oscillate about this point. The wages of
the day-labourer cannot rise higher, for otherwise settlers would turn
day-labourers; and they cannot sink lower, for otherwise day-labourers would
turn settlers.
The wages of industrial labourers are also, obviously, dominated by this general
rate of wages. For if the proceeds of labour in industry were larger than the
proceeds of labour on unclaimed land, agricultural labourers would turn to
industry, with the result that agricultural produce would become scarce and rise
in price, whereas industrial products, being super-abundant, would fall in
price. The rise of prices in agriculture and the fall of prices in industry
would bring about a re-arrangement of the wage scale, until wages had again been
equitably adjusted. And this readjustment would certainly be rapid, considering
the great number of migrating labourers who are indifferent whether they grow
sugar-beet or shovel coal.
Thus it is incontestable that if the proceeds of labour on freeland determine
the labour proceeds of the agricultural labourer they also determine labour
proceeds in general.
Wages cannot rise above the proceeds of labour on freeland, since freeland is
the only support of the farm-labourer in his wage-negotiations, or of the tenant
in his rent-negotiations, with the landowner. If the farm-labourer or tenant is
deprived of this support (say by suppression of his freedom of movement) he is
at the mercy of the landowner. But since freeland is the only support, it is
also true that no other circumstances can depress wages below these proceeds.
The proceeds of labour on freeland are, therefore, at once the maximum and the
minimum of wages in general.
The existing great differences in the individual proceeds of labour are by no
means inconsistent with this general rule. When the division of the product of
labour between landowners and workers has once been determined, the share that
falls to the workers is distributed automatically on a perfectly natural basis.
The varying remuneration is not arbitrary, but is adjusted entirely by the laws
of competition, of supply and demand. The more difficult or disagreeable the
work, the higher is the wage. For how is a man to be induced to choose the more
difficult or disagreeable of two tasks ? Only by the prospect of higher
labour-proceeds (which may, of course, consist of advantages and privileges
other than money). Thus if the workers need a teacher, a pastor or a forester,
their only course is to open their purses and grant salaries for these offices
which may greatly exceed their own proceeds of labour. Only in this way can they
induce someone to undertake the expense of having his sons educated for these
professions. If the supply of tachers and pastors is still insufficient, the
salaries must again be raised. If the workers have overshot the mark so that the
supply exceeds the demand, salaries will be reduced. And it is the same with all
trades requiring special training. The opposite happens when the workers need a
shepherd, a goose-girl or a boy to scare crows. If they were to offer for such
leisurely pursuits their own full proceeds of labour gained by hard work, every
townsman, teacher, pastor and farmer would apply for these posts. So a minimum
wage is offered for the herding of the geese, and this minimum is increased
until someone is willing to accept the job. The workers also need a merchant to
buy their products and to sell them whatever goods they want. This worker (merchant)
must also be granted a wage, in the shape of commercial profit, sufficient to
induce someone to devote himself to this harassing profession.
Thus the basis for the adjustment of all wages is always the proceeds of labour
on freeland. Upon this basis is built the whole structure of fine gradations in
the proceeds of labour up to the highest-paid occupations. Every change in the
basis is therefore transmitted to the whole superstructure, just as an
earthquake makes itself felt up to the weather-cock on the steeple.
Our proof that the doctrine of the "iron wage" is unsound is not yet,
indeed, complete, for the "iron wage", though not caused by private
ownership of land, might still be caused by capital. That capital does not
possess this power is obvious, however, from the frequent fluctuations of wages
(a really "iron" wage could not fluctuate). Why capital does not
possess this power we shall demonstrate later (see Part V, The Free-Money Theory
of Interest). If capital had power to reduce the proceeds of labour on freeland
to a minimum corresponding to the "iron wage", the yield of capital,
as expressed in the rate of interest, would necessarily share the fluctuations
to which the product of labour on freeland is obviously subject. But this is not
the case, for, as we shall show later, pure interest, which is here in question,
is a remarkably stable quantity, so remarkably stable, indeed, that we are fully
justified in speaking of an "iron" return on capital. So if besides
this fixed quantity of interest, wages were also a fixed quantity, where - if
rent moves on independent lines - would be the reservoir to collect the
fluctuations of the product of labour?
In making up his accounts, the settler on freeland must enter
a charge for interest on his working capital. Interest must be separated from
the proceeds of his labour, no matter whether the capital is his own or borrowed.
For interest has nothing in common with labour; it is governed by entirely
different laws.
And the working landowner must also make this separation of capital-interest
from the proceeds of his labour.
If both settlers on freeland and farmers on rented land have to pay the same
rate of interest for the necessary capital, it might be imagined that the rate
of interest had no effect on rent. But that is an error. With labour and means
of production any amount of new land can be created, often in close proximity to
cities. And the lower the rate of interest, the easier it is to reclaim waste
tracts. The employer demands from the reclaimed land only an amount of interest
equal to the rent of a field bought for the same capital outlay. With freeland
of the first and second classes freight sometimes swallows up the larger part of
the product of labour, but with reclaimed freeland it is capital-interest that
absorbs the expected rent. Whatever the nature of the proposed reclamation,
whether it is the drainage of the Zuider Zee, recently decided upon, or the
cultivation of moorland, or the clearing of virgin forests, or the irrigation of
deserts, or the blasting and removal of rocks, the first question is always the
amount of interest on the capital required, which is then compared with the rent
demanded for land of the same quality. If the rate of interest is high, the
comparison Will be discouraging, and the moor will be left uncultivated. If, on
the other hand, the rate of interest is low, the undertaking will promise
success. If the rate of interest fell from 4 to 1%, for example, many land
improvements which cannot be undertaken today would become profitable.
With interest at 1% it would pay to turn the water of the Nile into the Arabian
desert, to dam off the Baltic and pump it dry, to put the Luneburg Heath under
glass for the culture of cocoa and pepper. With interest at 1% the farmer could
also plant orchards where today he cannot do so because of the interest he would
have to pay for 5 or 10 years on the capital invested while waiting for the
future harvests. In a word, at 1 % it would be possible and profitable to bring
all deserts, swamps and moors into cultivation. All the above proposals are not,
of course, to be taken literally.)
A fall of the rate of interest would not only enlarge the area under cultivation,
it would also enable men to extract double or treble the amount of produce from
the present area through extended use of machinery, construction of roads,
replacing of hedges by fences, construction of pumping stations for irrigation,
drainage of the soil, planting of orchards, provision of appliances to protect
the fields from frost and a thousand similar improvements. This, again, would
necessitate a reduction of the cultivated area, and make freeland, the great
menace to rent, more accessible.
A reduction of the rate of interest would, further, allow transport-facilities
for wheat from abroad, (seaports, canals, ocean steamers, railways, silos) to be
run more cheaply, which would lower the freight charges on the produce of
freeland. And every dollar saved here means a dollar less for rent. Now the
interest on the money invested in means of transport constitutes a very
considerable part of freight charges. For the European railways in 1888, with an
average rate of interest of 3.8%, the ratio between working costs (upkeep of the
permanent way, salaries and wages, coal, etc.) and interest was 135:115.
Interest, therefore, very nearly , equalled the running costs, so that a
reduction of the rate of interest from 4 to 3% would have allowed a reduction of
the freight charges of nearly one eighth.
Running costs = 4, interest on capital = 4, freight charges = 8
" = 4, " = 3, " = 7
" = 4, " = 2, " = 6
" = 4, " = 1, " = 5
" = 4, " = 0, " = 4
That is to say, with interest at 0% railway freights might be reduced by one
half. With ocean freights the ratio of 9 costs to interest is not the same,
although here, too, interest plays an important part: ships, working capital,
harbours, canals (Panama, Suez), coaling stations, equipment of coal mines etc.
- all this demands the regular rate of interest, and this interest is a
component of freights, a charge on the labour-proceeds of freeland-settlers of
the first and second classes, which are of such decisive importance for wages
and rent.
Thus the reduction or elimination of interest would reduce freights by one half,
and in this manner freeland would, economically speaking, be brought 50% nearer,
the competition of foreign wheat becoming correspondingly keener.
But what would happen to rent if the arable area close at hand were multiplied
in this manner beyond the need for it ? What would happen to rent if freeland,
which determines wages, could be increased at pleasure, and that too, close at
hand, so that the difference between the product of labour of the
freeland-farmer and the proceeds of his labour became less and less ? Why
emigrate to far-off Canada, to Manitoba, and from there ship wheat burdened with
freight costs, to Holland, if we are able to grow the wheat on the soil of our
own Zuider Zee? If the rate of interest falls to 3, 2, 1 or 0%, every country
will be able to provide bread for its population. The limit to intensive
cultivation is set by interest. The lower the rate of interest, the more
intensive is the cultivation of the soil.
We can here observe the close alliance that exists between interest and rent. So
long as there are wastes, marshes and deserts to reclaim, so long as land can be
technically improved, a high rate of interest, the ideal of the capitalist, is
at the same time the bulwark of the landowner. If the rate of interest fell to
zero, rent would not, indeed, disappear completely, but it would be dealt a
staggering blow.
of a fall of interest on the rent of building land is complex. Interest on the
building capital is a far larger component of house-rent than is the ground-rent
(in the country and in small towns the ground-rent is often less than 5 % of the
rent of a house, whereas interest on the building capital in such cases forms
90% of the total rent). A fall of interest to 1 % or 0 % would therefore mean a
great reduction of house-rent, and this of course would react on the amount of
accommodation claimed by the individual families. The masses which today,
because of high house-rents resulting from interest, must content themselves
with very inadequate housing accommodation, would demand, and be able to pay for,
roomier dwellings. But roomier dwellings mean larger building sites and
therefore increased ground-rents. On the other hand a fall in the rate of
interest would reduce railway and train fares, and the consequent shifting of
the population to the suburbs would tend to counteract the rise of ground-rents
in the city).
The wage of the average worker is equal to the proceeds of
labour of the average cultivator of freeland and is entirely determined by these
proceeds. Every modification in the proceeds of labour of the cultivator of
freeland is transmitted to wages, no matter whether such modifications are
brought about by technical improvements, by scientific discoveries, or by
legislation.
The so-called "iron law" of wages is therefore an illusion. For the
individual, the wage oscillates about the amount mentioned under 1. It may rise
above this amount in the case of specially efficient work, but it may also fall
short of it, just as it may even fall short of the minimum standard of existence.
The whole wage-scale for skilled work up to the highest levels is based on the
labour-proceeds of the cultivator of freeland.
Rent on land is what remains of the produce of the land after deducting wages
(and capital interest). As the amount of this deduction (wage) is determined by
the proceeds of labour on land, rent is also determined by the proceeds of
labour of the freeland-farmer.
Interest is the close ally of rent.
It cannot be asserted without qualification that technical progress always
benefits rent. The contrary is often true. Progress and poverty are not
necessarily coupled. Progress and growing general prosperity as often go hand in
hand.
Nor can it be definitely stated whether the burden of a tax on land can, or
cannot be shifted. The question can be definitely answered only when the
destination of the revenue from the land-tax is indicated. The land-tax may hit
rent twice (first, through the tax itself, secondly, through the increase of
wages) or it may benefit rent by more than its amount.
If the yield of the tax on rent is employed for the benefit of the cultivators
of freeland, for instance as a premium on imported grain or as a subsidy for the
cultivation of waste land, the State, if it wishes, can confiscate rent
completely. The burden of a tax on rent, when the yield of the tax is so
employed, cannot be shifted.
Figure 1. The price of Agricultural land.
The price of land increases: With increase of quality and agricultural prices.
With decrease of wage-rates and rate of interest.
Whether wheat comes from Canada, from Argentina, from
Siberia, or from a neighbouring farm, whether it be the duty-burdened wheat of a
toiling German emigrant or duty-protected wheat of a wealthy Pomeranian squire,
does not concern the miller. If the quality is the same, so also is the price.
This is true of all commodities. Nobody inquires about the cost of production of
the goods offered for sale; everybody is indifferent about their origin. It
makes no difference whether one man has been enriched by them and another ruined;
if the quality is the same, so is the price. This is clearly seen in the case of
coins. Nobody inquires where, when, or how the gold of the individual coins was
obtained. One coin may have been bloodstained plunder, another the product of a
toil-worn gold digger, but they circulate indifferently side by side.
Whatever the difference in the costs of production of the individual competing
commodities - the price remains the same. This is known to everyone who uses raw
materials, and it is known also to the owner of the land on which the raw
materials can be raised. If, for example, a city needs paving stones for a new
street, the proprietor of the nearest quarry will at once estimate, the distance
from the street to the nearest free quarry of equally good paving stones. He
will then calculate the cost of carrying the stones from there to the street
where they are needed, and the price is made. This price the city will have to
pay, because only from this price upwards can competition come into play, and
competition determines price. (The wages in both quarries are assumed to be the
same, and may therefore be here left out of account).
If, however, direct competition is entirely lacking, if there is no free quarry
within reachable distance, and the proprietor in consequence demands excessive
prices for his paying stones, competition will be sustained by substitutes, in
this case, say, wood-pavement, macadam, gravel, asphalt, or a railway; or the
construction of the street may be abandoned. In the latter case the advantage
expected by the city from the construction of the street would be the only
competition which the proprietor of the quarry need take into account.
The same is true of all other raw materials without exception. If someone
requires lime for a cement factory, clay for a brickyard, bark for a tannery,
coal, iron ore, wood, water, building stones, sand, oil, mineral water, wind for
his windmill, sun for his sanatorium, shade for his summer-house, warmth for his
grapes, frost for his skating rink, the landowner who happens to be in
possession of these gifts of nature will exact payment for them, just as does
the quarry-owner for his paving stones, and always on exactly the same principle.
The circumstances may be different in each separate case; competition of
substitutes may limit the greed of the land-owner to a greater or less degree;
but always the same law holds good: the landowner exploits the advantages which
the products, the situation or the nature of his property offer, in such a
manner as to leave the purchaser for his labour only what he would have obtained
if he had been forced to procure his raw material from waste land, from the
desert, or from freeland.
From these considerations we deduce a proposition which is of great importance
for the general law of wages:
The product of the poorest, remotest and therefore often ownerless sources of
raw materials, loaded with freight charges and with the wages paid to work the
more favoured sources of similar materials, forms the basis of the price of
these materials. Whatever the owners of the favoured sources save in the cost of
production, is rent.
The consumer has to pay for all the products of the earth, for all raw materials,
as if they had been produced on waste land at great expense, or conveyed at
great expense from ownerless land.
If the product of a man's work on the poorest soil were equal to the minimum of
what man needs to subsist, the private ownership of land would make the "
iron law of wages " a reality; but as we have seen, such is not the case.
For this reason, but only for this reason, can wages rise above the minimum of
existence.
The ground-rent of cities, which in our industrial age very nearly equals the
total rent on agricultural land, is determined on exactly the same principle,
though in somewhat different circumstances.
The value of the land upon which Berlin is built was estimated in 1901 at 2911
million marks which, with interest at 4% corresponds to a rent of 116 millions.
This sum alone, distributed over the 4 million hectares of the province of
Brandenburg, is equal to a rent of 30 marks a hectare. With the ground-rent of
the other towns of the province added, the urban rent may amount to about 40
marks a hectare, a sum which, considering the poverty of the soil and the large
areas of water, swamp and forest, possibly exceeds the rent on agricultural
land. The position of the province of Brandenburg, a region with poor soil yet
containing the capital of the German Empire is, indeed, exceptional;
nevertheless these figures show the great importance of urban ground-rent at the
present day.
These figures are likely to surprise many readers; but, as someone has justly
remarked: it is becoming doubtful whether, measured by the rental, our great
landed estates are not to be looked for in Berlin rather than, as hitherto, in
Silesia.
How is this curious phenomenon to be accounted for; what determines the rent of
building land, and what is its relation to the general law of wages ?
In the first place we must explain why men congregate in cities in spite of the
high ground-rent; why do they not spread all over the country ? Calculated by
the above figures the average ground-rent for every inhabitant of Berlin is 58
marks, that is, for families of 5 persons 290 marks yearly; an expense which is
entirely avoided in the country, for the ground-rent of the average country
cottage is so trifling that it could be paid with the contents of its
earth-closet. And the hygienic advantages of life in the country contrast
strikingly with the miserable housing conditions in towns. There must, therefore,
be other weighty reasons to make people prefer the town.
If we assume that the social advantages of the town are cancelled by its
disadvantages (bad air, dust, noise and numerous other offences to our senses),
all that is left to balance the expense of urban life is the economic advantage
of living in a town. The interdependence and co-operation of the city industries
must afford advantages over isolated industry in the country which in the case
of Berlin counterbalance the 116 millions of ground-rent. If it were not so, the
growth of cities would be quite unaccountable.
No industry can be established in the country which, from its seasonal character,
occupies many workers today, and few or none tomorrow; for the worker must work
all the year round. In the city the varying demand for labour in the different
industries is more or less levelled, so that workmen dismissed by one
manufacturer are engaged by another. In this way a workman has greater security
against unemployment in a town than in the country.
In the country the manufacturer lacks opportunity for the exchange of ideas, the
stimulus given by intercourse with other businessmen. Workmen trained in
different factories and acquainted with various methods are also a considerable
asset to the city manufacturer as compared with his competitor in the country.
Thrown entirely on his own resources, and compelled to employ workmen deprived
of intercourse with workmen from other industries and other countries, the
country manufacturer is apt to lag behind in the adoption of improvements. He
also often lacks the facilities afforded by the city for the sale of his
products. Purchasers from all parts of the country and from other countries
flock to the city where they find everything they need, collected in one place.
The city manufacturer is visited by foreign customers who draw attention to the
consumers' wishes, and moreover give him valuable information about market
conditions, prices, and so forth. The country manufacturer is deprived of all
this. Instead of being visited by his customers he must sacrifice time and money
in travelling to visit them. He must collect his information about prices of raw
materials, market conditions abroad and the solvency of his customers in
round-about ways that are often anything but reliable.
Furthermore he is forced to lay in much larger stocks of raw material than his
competitor in town who is able to procure everything immediately when needed;
and if through some oversight the country manufacturer runs short of some
article, perhaps only a screw, the whole factory is brought to a standstill
until the missing part has been sent from "town". Or if a machine
breaks down, a mechanic may have to be summoned from town, and until he arrives
the factory is again idle.
In short, the disadvantages connected with the factory itself, with the workmen,
the purchase of raw materials and the sale of finished goods, are so many that
the country manufacturer forced to compete with a rival in town cannot possibly
pay the same wages as the latter. Thus all that he and his workmen save in
ground-rent is deducted from the proceeds of their labour.
Hence the only industries that can develop in the country are those which
require so much space that all disadvantages are counter-balanced by the saving
on ground-rent; or those which cannot be carried on in towns (saw-mills,
brickyards, rolling mills) or are forbidden by the police for hygienic reasons (lime-kilns,
powder-mills, tanneries, etc.); or those which, having a simple technical
organisation, allow the manager to establish his commercial headquarters in
town. In every other case the town is preferred.
We know therefore where the money to pay the 116 millions of marks ground-rent
of the city of Berlin comes from, and we also know what sets the limit to the
growth of cities. The advantages of combined work have been calculated in money
and pocketed as ground-rent by the landlords.
If the city grows, its economic advantages grow, and ground-rents grow also. And
if ground-rents grow out of proportion to the advantages of the city, its growth
is interrupted.
If you wish to enjoy the advantages afforded by the city for your trade, you
must pay the landlords for these advantages; otherwise you are free to establish
your factory, shop, or dancing hall in the woods and fields. Calculate what is
more advantageous, and act accordingly. Nobody prevents you from settling
outside the city gates. If you can induce your customers to tramp out to you
through rain and snow, dust and mud, and there to pay the same price as in the
centre of the city, so much the better for you. If you think it unlikely, then
pay the ground-rent and establish yourself in town. You have indeed another
possibility, you can try selling your goods cheaper outside the city. Some
customers will be attracted by the cheaper prices; but where is the advantage?
What you save on rent, you lose in the price of the goods sold.
Ground-rents are thus determined by precisely the same law that governs the
rents of agricultural land and raw materials. All the advantages of the city (among
which we should mention the division of labour), are reaped by the
ground-landlord. Just as German wheat is sold for the price it would have
fetched if it had been grown in Siberia and taxed at the frontier, so the goods
produced in a city must be exchanged at the prices they would have fetched if
loaded with all the disadvantages of goods produced far away from industrial
centres.
Agricultural rent captures all the advantages of situation and nature, leaving
waste-land and wilderness for the cultivator; city ground-rent claims for itself
all the advantages of society, of mutual aid, of organisation, of education, and
reduces the proceeds of those engaged in city industry and commerce to the level
of producers isolated in the country.
The products that remain after deduction of rent and
capital-interest, form the wage-fund to be shared among all workers (day-labourers,
clergymen, merchants, physicians, servants, kings, craftsmen, artists). When
everyone is free to choose his trade, the division is made according to the
personal capacity of each, by demand and supply. If choice of occupation were
completely free (it is not, but might be) everyone would actually obtain the
"largest" share in the distribution. For everyone tries to obtain the
largest share, and the size of the share is determined by demand and supply or,
ultimately, by the choice of occupation.
Thus the relative amount of the wage depends on the choice of occupation, that
is, on the individual. The absolute amount of the wage on the contrary, is quite
independent of the individual, and is determined by the amount of the wage-fund.
The larger the contributions of the individual workers to the wage-fund, the
larger will be the share for each. The number of workers is irrelevant; if there
are more workers, the absolute size of the wage-fund grows, but the number of
those entitled to a share grows likewise.
We now know the amount contributed by the different categories of workers to the
wage-fund:
The contribution of agricultural workers is equal to the sum of products which
an equal number of agricultural workers could grow on freeland - less freight,
interest and import-duties, which we have to conceive as being reckoned in
produce.
The contribution of other producers of raw materials is equal to the sum of
products which they could bring to market from the poorest, remotest, and
therefore ownerless sources - less interest.
The contribution of industrial workers, merchants, physicians, artists, is equal
to the sum of products which they could produce without the advantages of
mutuality and organisation, and isolated from populous centres - less interest.
If we pool all these products and distribute them according to the present-day
wage-scale, everyone gets exactly the products which he can actually procure in
the shops and markets with his present wages.
The difference between this amount and the total produce of the aggregate work
performed goes to make up rent and capital-interest.
What, then, can the workers (always in the broadest sense of the term) do to
enlarge the wage-fund, to obtain a real all-round increase of wages, which
cannot be neutralised by an increase in the cost of living ?
The answer is simple: they must keep closer watch on their wage-fund; they must
protect it from parasites. The workers must defend their wage-fund as bees and
marmots defend theirs. The whole product of labour, with no deduction for rent
and interest, must go into the wage-fund and be distributed to the last crumb
among its creators. And this can be achieved by two reforms which we have named
"Free-Land" and "Free-Money".